Linki
- ,,(...)człowiek nigdy nie wyrobi sobie o nikim właściwego pojęcia .Stwarza obraz i kontent.
- Intruzi Michael Marshall E-BOOK, Fantastyka, fantasy
- Insight Intermediate Student's Book Podręcznik dla szkół ponadgimnazjalnych Wildman Jayne, Podręczniki, lektury
- Instrukcja montarzu subwofera xc90 instruction VCC-138791-1 (1), E-Book's
- Inteligencja emocjonalna. Poradnik dla rodziców Beatriz Serrano Garrido e-book, Poradniki
- Ingarden - Wstep do Fenomenologii Husserla wyklad 1, e-book, Filozofia, Ingarden Roman
- Informatyka SP KL 4-6. Podręcznik multimedialny pendrive + zbiór zadań. Zajęcia komputerowe. Lubię to! 2012 Kęska Michał e-book, Inne
- Informatyka Europejczyka. Program nauczania do zajęć komputerowych w szkole podstawowej w edukacji w Danuta Kiałka e-book, Podręczniki, lektury
- Indie. Mapa Marco Polo w skali 12 500 000 praca zbiorowa E-BOOK, Turystyka, mapy, atlasy
- Instrukcja stosowania kas rejestrujących z wzorcową dokumentacją i nowymi ewidencjami - Grzegorz Tomala e-book, B jak Biznes i ekonomia
- In-depth analysis of the viral threats with OpenOf#ce.org uments, Hacking and IT E-Book Dump Release
- zanotowane.pl
- doc.pisz.pl
- pdf.pisz.pl
- nie-szalona.htw.pl
|
[ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ] Indigenous Knowledge Systems, The Cognitive Revolution, and Agricultural Decision Making Christina H. Gladwin Christina H. Gladwin is Associate Professor in the Food and Resource Economics Department at the University of Florida, Gainesville. Her research interests include the cognitive relationship between norms, plans, and decision processes and large-scale shifts in norms and choice. The research for this paper was initiated while she was a Rockefeller post-doe assigned to the International Fertilizer Development Center. ABSTRACT: Increasingly, it is acceptedwisdomfor agricultural scientists to getfeedback from indigenous peoples--peas- ants--about new improved seeds and biotechnologies before their official releasefrom the experiment station. What is not yet accepted udsdom is the importance of cognitive science to research onfarmer decision making, especially of the type "Why don't they adopt." In this paper, the impact of the cognitive revolution on models offarmer decision making is described, and decision making models before and after the cognitive revolution are contrasted. An example of a decision model after the cognitive revolution is given by the Malawifarmer's decision whether to use chemical fertilizers or organic fertilizers or both. Results of testing the model show that in Malawi, smallholdsrs' lack of capital and credit are more important factors constraining use of chemical fertilizers than are indigenous beliefs in organic fertilizers or fears of a future dependency on chemicals. The schoolofthoughtnowdubbed IKS, indigen- ous knowledge systems, aims to elicit the expert systems ofindigenouspeoples--peasants---whoare sometimes not thought ofas experts. These knowl- edge systems are brought back to agricultural re- search centers and ministries of agriculture and used to educate agricultural scientists and policy makers so that they can design better technologies and policies to improve peasants' standards of liv- ing. The idea that local knowledge is a valuable resource to be understood and used to alleviate poverty is beginning to diffuse throughout the Third World in practical applications to develop- ment problems, and in the academic literature, as is evidencedby the papers in this volumeand others (Brokensha, 1989). Starting with the collection of the same name, IKS scholars have described the expert systems of peasants to do any number of things: to farm, to fertilize, to manage their soils and natural resources in a sustainable way, to adopt or not adopt new '~improved"technologies, to take risks, to make a living (Brokensha, Warren and Werner, 1980). Farming systems programs in in- ternational agricultural research centers have seen the value ofknowing'~ow the farmers think" about their crops, pests, forests, and water resources (CIMMYT, 1984; Matlon, Cantrell, King, and Be- noit-Cattin, 1984), before agricultural scientistsde- sign improvedtechnologiesfor them. Increasingly, it is accepted wisdomfor an agronomistto get feed- back from peasants about new improved seeds and biotechnologies before their official release from the experiment station. It is also generally recognized that the goals of the IKS school go way back to the anthropologist Malinowski (1922) who aimed to "grasp the native's point ofview, his relation to life, to realize his vision of his world." To see the insiders' world through the insiders' eyes has long been the aim of enthog- raphers, whose work describes a culture from the "native's" or insider's point of view and not from the researcher's or outsider's point ofview (Sprad- 32 Gladwin: Indigenous Knowledge Systems ley, 1979). To minimize the researcher's own ethnocentricity, i.e., the viewingofanother culture through the lens of one's own cultural values and assumptions, the enthnographer seeks to learn from people, to be taught by them like a child is taught. The aim is to discover the cultural meaning of the insiders' relationships, native terms, rules, and way of life (Spradley, 1979: 3). This is a far different goal from that of collecting data about people and testing a model based on the outsider's view. Models of indigenous knowledge systems should thus contain "emic" categories, i.e., units of meaning drawn from the culture bearers them- selves, which can be contrasted with "etic" catego- ries which may have meaning for researchers but need not have meaningfor the people ofthe specific culture under study (Pike, 1954; Harris, 1979: 32- 45). computer; its short-term memory is limited to roughly 5 to 7 items at a time. Indeed, people seem to categorize or discretize variables, rather than deal with continuous quantitative variables as a real computer does. People use logic rather than perform complicated mathematical operations as a real computer does. The limited "rehersal buffer" of humans affects the way people organize their language and thought processes, such that they are "nierarchially" organized (Miller, Galanter, and Pribram, 1960). This revolutionary idea was taken up by the linguist Noam Chomsky, whose '"crees" or transfor- mational grammars spread to most knownlanguages around the world. In the field of artifical intelli- gence, it stimulated scientists to invent computer programs called "expert systems" which mirrored the way humans think, rather than expect humans to think like sophisticated computers. In psychol- ogy, the revolutionstimulated newtheories ofprob- lem solving (Neweli and Simon, 1972) and plans or scripts (Schank and Abelson, 1977), and caused the abandonment of decision making models of "ex- pected utility" in favor of theories of "elimination- by-aspects" and "preferencetrees" (Tversky, 1972; Kahneman and Tversky, 1972, 1982; Tversky and Kahneman, 1981). In anthropology, in resulted in the spread of cognitivemodels oftaxonomies, schematas, and de- cision processes, which replaced the use of psychological traits and raw-shock tests to explain cultural differences. Given the aims of ethnograp- hers to modelthe insiders' point ofview and knowl- edge, it was not surprising that the cognitive rev- olution found the field of anthropology a fertile ground to grow in. The products of cognitive an- thropology can now be seen in frame analysis (Frake, 1964), taxonomic analysis (Berlinand Kay, 1969), componential analysis (Romney and D'An- drade, 1964), schematas or folkmodels(D'Andrade, 1981; 1987; H. Gladwin, 1974; Quinn 1990), plans or scripts (Werner and Schoepfle, 1987), and deci- sion tree models or tables. Before these models are described, a look at what decision models were like before the cognitive revolution is in order. What is not yet accepted wisdom is the impor- tance of cognitive science to this school of thought and agricultural development policies, and the in- fluence of '%he cognitive revolution," which, since the 1950s and 1960s, has shaken the foundations of six social sciences: artificial intelligence, anthro- pology, linguistics, neuroscience, psychology, and philosophy (Gardner, 1985). Perhaps agricultural scientists who are used to empirical laboratory ex- periments are uncomfortablein realizingthat farm- ers' acceptance of their new biotechnologies partly depends on the mystery ofhow the human mind-- the ultimate black box--works. Yet as more and more agricultm~al scientists giveup the naivenotion that their technologies will automatically diffuse, more and moreresearch on farmer decisionmaking, especially of the type '~¢hy don't they adopt," is done. One lesson gleaned from the adoption litera- ture, by now too vast to adequately cite, is that the success of efforts to predict farmers' decision mak- ing depends on the underlyingassumptions that are made about cognition, i.e., the thought process it- self. These assumptions changed drastically with the cognitive revolution. Before the cognitive rev- olution, agriculturaldecision modelsweremathemat- ically sophisticated, with risk-aversion often being measured by the sign of the second differential (Schoemaker, 1982); after the cognitive revolution, simpler decision rules and trees replaced optimiza- tion ofacontinuous, twice-differentiablefunction. Agricultural Decision Making Before the Cognitive Revolution In the field ofagricultural decisionmaking, long dominated by (agricultural) economists, decision models were quantitative, linear-additive, and often normative (e.g., linear programmingmodels, expected value and expected utility models, sto- chastic dominance) but typically not empirically grounded. They were not usually tested against a set of choice data to see how well they predicted The Cognitive Revolution Scientific assumptions about cognition were radically changed in 1956 with the publication of a seemingly-innocuous article entitled, "The Magic Number Seven, Plus or Minus Two,"by the psycho- logist George Miller. Miller's new idea was that the human computeris oflimited capacity, unlike a real 33 AGRICULTURE AND HUMAN VALUES--SUMMER 1989 the choices ofindividuals in a group (see Anderson, 1979; Anderson, Dillon, and Hardaker, 1977). In- stead, they were either used as behavioral assump- tions in a model of aggregate supply or demand, or as normative models to tell people how they should make decisions (Raiffa, 1968), or tested to see if they "fit" the observed behavior of one '~represen- tative" individual (Benito, 1976). They were not empiricallytested against choice data because the test was usually so complicated that it was not worth the effort. For example, in a test of the expected utility model, the researcher had to measure each individual's "utility function," which could vary in shape across individuals de- pending on how risk-averse they were; and then independently measure each individual's "subjec- tive" probability distribution which differed from the objective probability distribution. This proved to be such a job that it was rarely done; but text- books described how it could be done (Anderson, Dillon, and Hardaker, 1977). When it was done, errors arose due to inconsistencies(Officerand Hal- ter, 1968), or when midway through the experi- ment, riskless gambles were replaced byriskygam- bles, suggesting that even the same individual might have morethan one utilityfunction(Tversky, 1967). rules do not produce an ordinal utility function, as micro-economictheory assumes. Cognitivists even objectedto the linear-additive decision models called probit analysis and logit analysis, which have the advantage over expected utility and linearprogrammingmodelsofbeingtest- able with data on choicesmade by manyrather than one individual. Unfortunately, they also are not cognitively-realistic models of the choice process. No-one assigns weights to several variables and then adds them up to determine which of several outcomesis better; people comparealternatives one dimension at a time. But probit and logit analyses do have the advantage of providing a statistical test; they thus can be used alongside rule-based decision models to show whether there is a signifi- cant correlation between a particular independent variable (or decision criterion in the nile) and the decision outcome chosen. In this way, they can pro- vide an indirect test of a rule-based model (Mukhopadhyay, 1984). Unfortunately, they can provide this test for only a few of the variables or criteria in an individual's decision process. Cognitivists also rejected the quantitative na- ture ofdecisionvariables in a probit or Iogit analysis or linear programming model. Following Miller (1956), they claimed that decision makers use dis- crete decisioncriteriainreal-lifechoices, evenwhen faced with a variable amenable to quantification such as cost. The decision criteria used in decision tree models are thus not continuous quantitative variables; they are discrete constraints that must be passed or satisfied (e.g., Is cost ofcar < $4000?) or orders and semi-orders ofalternatives on aspects (e.g., Is cost of carl < cost of car2?). An alternative is assumed to be a set of aspects or constraints (Lancaster, 1966; Tversky, 1972; Gladwin, 1980), but criteriaare discrete. An algebraic form ofchoice model results. The decision process is also assumed to be deterministic rather than probabilistic: an al- ternative either passes the criteria or constraints with a probability of one or it does not. There are thus no probabilities otherthan 1 or 0--facing the individual on each branch, as in Raiffa (1968). A decision tree is thus a sequence ofdiscrete decision criteria, all ofwhich have to be passed along a path to a particular outcome or choice. Agricultural Decision Making After the Cognitive Revolution Cognitive psychologists and anthropologists in the 1970s rejected the expected utility theory of choice, and searched for more cognitively-realistic models of the choice process. They claimed that people in real-life choice contexts don't make holis- tic assignments of utility or satisfaction to each al- ternative inthe choiceset, and separatelyformulate subjective probabilities (Quinn, 197~, and then pick the alternative with the most "expected utility" (Kahneman and Tversky, 1972, 1982). In line with Miller's results on the limitations of human compu- tational capacities, theyfeltthat decisionsare made in a decomposed fashion using relative compari- sons, because it is cognitively easier to compare alternatives on a piece-meal basis, i.e., one dimen- sion at a time (Schoemaker, 1982). Indeed, people do not rank order alternatives holistically when they make a decision. They just chose one out of several alternatives without ranking them (Quinn, 1971), in which case the decision model is what Arrow (1951) calls a "choice function not built up from orderings," i.e., simply a set ofrules. In some choice contexts, these rules may result in an incom- plete order (Gladwin, 1975) and intransitive perfer- ence structure (Tversky, 1969). In these cases, the Decision Tree Modeling Ethnographic decision tree modeling starts fromthe assumption that the decisionmakers them- selves are the experts on how they make the deci- sions they make. It uses ethnographic fieldwork techniques to elicit from the decision makers them- selves their decision criteria, which are then corn- 34 Gladwin: Indigenous Knowledge Systems bined in the formofa decisiontree, table, flowchart, or set of if-then rules or "expert systems" which can be programmed on the computer (Gladwin, 1989). There are thus two distinctivefeatures about the method: its reliance on ethnographic fieldwork techniques to elicit the decision criteria, and its insistence on a formal, testable, computer-based model of the decision process which is hierarchical or treelike in nature. Ethnographic decision tree modeling is not a black box technique like some quantitive methods (e.g., factor analysis, multidimensional scaling, cluster analysis). Because of its dependence on eliciting procedures, the model is culturally tuned by some specific group of individuals, and then tested against choice data from other individuals in the group. 1The form of a decision tree model is amazingly simple, with the choice alternatives in a set at the top of the tree, denoted by { } and the decision criteria at the nodes or diamonds of the tree denoted by < >, and the decision outcomes denoted by [ ] at the ends of the paths of the tree. The decision maker starts at the top of the tree and, independently of other decision makers, is asked the set ofquestionsinthe criteria at the nodes of the tree, and based on his or her responses is "sent down" the tree on a path to a particular out- come. Cognitiveanthropologistsinthe 1970s and 1980s applied these ideas to real-life choice contexts in a number of different cultures. These included economic decisions made by Ghanaian fish sellers in decidingbetween markets (H. Gladwin, 1971; C. Gladwin, 1975; Quinn, 1978), farmers' adoption de- cisions in Puebla, Mexico (C. Gladwin, 1976, 1977, 1979a, 1979b), California families' decisionsregard- ing the sexual division of labor within the family for daily routine tasks (Mukhopadhyay, 1984), farmers' croppingdecisions (Barlett, 1977; C. Glad- win, 1983), peasants' choice oftreatment forillness in Pichatero, Mexico (Young, 1980, 1981), U. S. car buyers' choice of cars (H. Gladwin and Murtaugh, 1984; Murtaugh and H. Gladwin, 1980), economic development decisions of the Navajo tribe (Schoepfle, Burton, and Morgan, 1984), and U. S. farmers' decisions to cut back production and sell land daring a farm crisis (Zabawa, 1984; C. Gladwin and Zabawa, 1984, 1986, 1987). In each case where the methodology of decision trees has been used, the predictability has been as high as 85 to 95 per- cent of the historical choice data used to test the model. These success rates are remarkable only because the pre-cognitive decision models of ac- cepted wisdom (e.g., expected utility) could not even be tested to see how well they could predict a set of choice data. A Real-Life Example: The Malawi Smallholder's Decision Between Chemical and Organic Fertilizers How do small-scalefarmers in the Third World decide whether or not to use chemical fertilizers? Why do or don't they use organic fertilizers(man- ure, compost, green manure) as substitutes for chemicals? Which constraints to chemical fertilizer use are more important: farmers' lack ofcapitalor credit,ortheirindigenous beliefsinorganic fertiliz- ers (manure/compost) as the right way to fertilize their crops, or their fear of dependency on chemi- cals? This decisionisa crucialone forAfrican govern- ments facinga '%od crisis"intheircitiesand trying toincrease thefood surplus produced by smallfarm- ers in the countryside, because food production is linked to quantity of fertilizerused on most food crops. It is even more important in a country like Malawi in southern A~ca thatisland-locked,faces high transport costs to the sea (due to the cutting of the Beira railroad line in Mozambique) and im- ports all chemical fertilizeror its feedstocks. It is a key decision for those policy makers interested in the potential of sustainable agriculture or low- input agriculture(Brush, 1989).The decisionmodel in figures la, lb, lc, and ld explains why some farmers use both chemical and organic fertilizer, while others use only chemical, while some use only organic (definedas animal manure, compost, orcer- tain kinds of green manure). It also tests whether the main reason fornonuse ofeitherkind offertilizer is simply farmers' lack ofcash or credit,as opposed to an indigenous trust in localorganic fertilizersor amore invidiousfearofdependency onchemicals. In April and May, 1987, the model was tested with choice data on fertilizeruse ofsmallholders in Malawi during personal interviews; the testsample was comprised of 40 farmers in three agricultural districts: Lilongwe, Kasungu, and Salima.~ Al- though farmers in this sample were on average big- ger, more experienced farmers than is the norm (with average landholdings of 3.02 ha.), in other respects the sample is fairly representative of Malawi smaUholders: 26 farmers were credit club members, and 14 were not; 22 farmers got credit for fertilizer in 1986/87, while 18 did not. Seventeen farmers were women householdheads, three were couples interviewed together, and 20 were male household heads; the sample has a high proportion of female household heads because Dixon (1982) estimates that women in Malawi perform about 50 percent ofthe agricultural labor. Ofthe 40 farmers interviewed, 33 were household heads. Questions about the sexual divisionoflabor and incomewithin the family revealed that groundnuts is a woman's 35 AGRICULTURE AND HUMAN VALUES--SUMMER 1989 cash crop while tobacco, cotton, and hybrid maize are men's cash crops, and local maize and beans are grown for the whole family's consumption. Because the outcome chosen by the farmer is different for different crops, this model is specific to the local variety of maize, which constitutes 90 percent of maize production and is the staple food crop. Also for simplicity of modeling, it is here as- sumed that every farmer incorporates some crop residues of maize during the "banking up" of soil around the secondary roots aider the second weed- ing and fertilizing. This use of crop residues is no doubt beneficial to the soft, but is not the same terrific stuff as animal manure or compost. Hence organic fertilizer here means manure and/or com- post and/or green manure, but not crop residues. The model posits that farmers must first pass a set ofsimple "elimination-by-aspects"constraints (Tversky, 1972) in figure la. They then must have a need or motivation to use either or both kinds of fertilizer (figure lb). They then pass to a set of resource constraints specific to each kind of fer- tilizer, and will use that kind if they satisfy or pass each constraint (figures lc and ld). Farmers will use both kinds of fertilizer if they think the crop needs both, and they pass both sets of resource constraints. Figure la.The DecisionBetween Organic and Chemical Fertiliz- ers on Local Maize: Stage 1 Constraints. 40 cases $ {Apply organic; chemical; both} ,Does your soil need or respond to either chemical , Eliminate or organic fertilizers? no Both I 0 cases yes l 2Does your local maize variety need either chemical or • Eliminate organic fertilizers? no Both I 0 cases yes 1 ~Do you let most of your land lie fallow for two or more years .... at a time so that afterwards you--*~nnunate don't need to apply chemical or yes Both organic fertilizers? 0 cases no, I need them afterwards ] to apply either chemical or no Both • Eliminate organic fertilizers this year? 8 cases I yes Elimination Criteria Farmers must first pass a simple set of con- straints in figure la which eliminate use of both organic and chemical fertilizers if: their type of soil doesn't need or respond to either kind of fertilizer (criterion 1), or their type oflocal maize seed doesn't need either kind of fertilizer (criterion 2), or they let most of their land lie fallow for two or more years so that after the fallow period it doesn't need either chemical or organic fertilizers (criterion 3), or they lack the cash or credit for either chemical or organic this year (criterion 4). If a farmer is eliminated at this first stage ofthe decisionprocess, he or she doesn't have to decide between organic and chemicalfertilizersbecause both are eliminated and the decision is simple. Go on to figure lb 32 cases fertilizer (criterion 6) and it is more profitable than organic, they are sent only to figure ld. In figure lc, farmers will apply organic fertilizer to local maize if: they have enough animals to make enough manure or compost to use on their local maize (or a crop (e.g., tobacco) rotated with local maize)8 every two or three years (criterion 8), or they can buy the manure/compostthey need (criter- ion 9) and they have or can borrow/rent an oxcart and oxen to carrythe manure/compostto their fields (criterion 10), and they have the time or (fun- or part-time) labor to carry it to their fields (criterion 12), which are not too far away to reach by oxcart (criterion 11). If all these constraints are passed, the model predicts that the farmer applies manure and/or compost to localize maize (or a crop rotated with local maize). If a farmer fails one constraint, the model predicts no manure/compost is applied. In figure ld, farmers will apply chemical fer- tilizer to local maize if: there was chemicalfertilizer available at the time needed, either to buy or get on credit (criterion 13), and the farmer had either Stage Two-Criteria Farmers who pass "stage 1" criteria do have a complicated decision, however, and continue on to stage-two criteria in figure lb. If they think that their local maize variety needs both kinds of fer- tftizer to produce good yields (criterion 5) they are sent on to both sets ofresource constraints in figures ic and ld. If they think local maize needs only or- ganic fertilizer (criterion 6) and it is more profitable than chemical, they are sent only to figure lc. Simi- larly, if they think local maize needs only chemical 36 'Have the [cash or credit
[ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ]
zanotowane.pldoc.pisz.plpdf.pisz.plzolka.keep.pl
|